FreshRSS

๐Ÿ”’
โŒ About FreshRSS
There are new available articles, click to refresh the page.
Before yesterdayYour RSS feeds

AI As A Writing Tool: Great Benefits, Major Pitfalls.

Written by Neil Levy

Large language models look set to transform every aspect of life over the coming decades. Some of these changes will be dramatic. Iโ€™m pretty unconcernedย by the apocalyptic scenarios that preoccupy some people, but much more worried about the elimination of jobs (interestingly, the jobs that seem likeliest to be eliminated are those that require the most training: we may see a reversal of status and economic position between baristas and bureaucrats, bricklayers and barristers). Here, though, Iโ€™m going to look at much less dramatic, and very much near term, effects that LLMs might have on academic writing. Iโ€™m going to focus on the kind of writing I do in philosophy; LLMs will have different impacts on different disciplines.

A number of academics, writing in academic journals and on Twitter, have suggested that LLMs could be used to streamline the writing process. As they envisage it, LLMs could take on the burden of writing literature reviews and overviews, leaving the human free to undertake the more creative work involving the generation and testing of hypotheses (here, too, though, the LLM might have a role: it could generate candidate hypotheses for the human to choose between and refine, for example).

As a proponent of what we might call extended cognition, the general idea is one to which Iโ€™m sympathetic. The extended mindย hypothesis is a metaphysical claim: on this hypothesis, mind can extend beyond the skull and into the artifacts that enable certain kinds of thinking (my smartphone might partially constitute my mind, when its reminders, navigational capacities, search functions, and so on, are sufficiently integrated into my cognitive activities). The extended cognition hypothesis is agnostic about metaphysics: it simply emphasises the degree to which our thought is offloaded onto the world, including artifacts. New technologies enable new kinds of thinking, and this has always been true. As Richard Feynman said, notes on paper arenโ€™t merely a record of thinking, โ€œnot really. Itโ€™s working. You have to work on paper, and this is paper.โ€

Extending cognition through new technologies opens cognitive horizons that are otherwise inaccessible to us. Supercomputers that perform millions of operations per second allow us to analyse data and perform mathematical calculations that were utterly closed to previous generations. But in opening up new horizons, new ways of extending thought can make others less accessible and have unwanted impacts on our native cognition. In The Phaedo, Plato expressed the fear that writing would undermine our capacity to remember things. He may have been right about its effects on our memory, but thatโ€™s more than compensated for by our increased capacity to record things externally. There are no guarantees, however, that changes will always be for the better.

The idea of a division of labor between the relatively routine and the creative imagined above, with the LLM taking on the first and the human (alone or in collaboration with the LLM) the second, is not unattractive. It can be tiresome to review a literature one already knows well. Sometimes, I find myself in the position of having to rewrite pretty much the same points Iโ€™ve made in a previous paper in an introductory section. Itโ€™s only norms against self-plagiarism that prevent me from cutting and pasting from the older paper to the newer one. Allowing the LLM to do the work of rephrasing is a tempting option. We might think that whatever other costs and benefits they have, getting them to do what we the drudge work is surely an unalloyed benefit.

Perhaps โ€“ perhaps โ€“ย itโ€™s a benefit overall, but itโ€™s notย an unalloyed benefit. While we may approach a paper with a hypothesis in mind, and think of the introductory sections as merely sketching out the terrain, the relationship between that sketch and the meat of the paper is not always so straightforward. Sometimes, in rephrasing and summarizing ideas that I thought I already knew well, I discover relations between them I hadnโ€™t noticed, or a lack of clarity that hadnโ€™t struck me before. These realisations may lead to the reframing of the initial hypothesis, or the generation of a new hypothesis, or simply greater clarity than I had previously. What I took to be mere drudge work canโ€™t be easily isolated from the more creative side of thought and writing.

More generally, the drudge work lays down the bedrock for creative activity. If I had never attempted to review and synthesise the work that appears in the review section of a paper, I wouldnโ€™t know it well enough to be able to generate some of the hypotheses I go on to explore. That drudge work is an essential developmental stage. Itโ€™s also a developmental stage for a set of skills at navigating a terrain. This isย a generalizable skill, one we can apply in future to different material and different debates. It may be that those who have already developed such skills โ€“ those who became academically mature before the advent of LLMs โ€“ can outsource drudge work at a smaller cost than those who have not yet developed this set of skills. Perhaps doing the task for oneself, boring though it may be, is necessary for a while, before we throw away the ladder weโ€™ve climbed.

Iโ€™ve got no doubt that LLMs can and will be incorporated into academic writing, in ways and with effects weโ€™re only beginning to imagine. Externalizing thought is extremely productive: itโ€™s always been productive to write down your thoughts, because externalizing them allows us to reconfigure them, and to see connections that we mightnโ€™t otherwise have noticed. The more complex the material, the greater the need to externalize. LLMs allow for a near instantaneous kind of externalization: we might regenerate multiple versions of a thought weโ€™ve written once, and the permutations might allow us to see new connections. LLMs can also be used to generate new candidate hypotheses, to identify gaps in the literature, to synthesise and visualise data, and who yet knows what else? Perhaps the day will come โ€“ perhaps it will even be soon โ€“ when AI replaces the human researcher altogether. For now, itโ€™s a powerful tool, perhaps even a partner, in the research process.

Some of those who have worried about the singularity โ€“ the postulated moment when AI design takes off, with ever more intelligent AIs designing even more intelligent AIs, leaving us humans in their dust โ€“ have proposed we might prevent human obsolescence by merging with the machines, perhaps even uploading our minds to artificial neural networks. I donโ€™t know whether the singularity or human obsolescence are real threats, and Iโ€™m very sceptical about mind uploading. Whatever the prospects might be for mind uploading, right now we can integrate AIs into our thinking. We may not stay relevant for ever, and we may never merge with the machines, but right now theyโ€™re powerful tools for extending our cognition. They might homogenize prose and lead to a loss of creativity, or they might lead to an explosion of new approaches and ideas. Theyโ€™re certain to have unanticipated costs, but the benefits will probably be much greater.

Inevitably, I ran this blogpost through an AI tool โ€“ the free version of Quillbot. It identified one or two typos, which of course I corrected. It also made a number of stylistic suggestions. I accepted almost none of them, but several led me to think I ought to rephrase the passage. Perhaps thatโ€™s not a model for how AI might be useful for writing right now.

Is Authenticity Coherent?

By Neil Levy

Authenticity is a widely espoused ideal; often under that name but also under other labels. People take pride in being individuals, set apart from the crowd, in not following the herd, in thinking for themselves. To be accused of conformism stings.ย 

But letโ€™s think about a very standard example of inauthenticity: the suburban accountant. He (itโ€™s almost always a โ€˜heโ€™ in these examples) works in a 9-5 job he commutes to, he drives a mid-range car and once a year he takes a vacation to Disneyland with his wife and 2 children. Carl Elliot has influentially argued that any enhancement that reconciled a person to that life would leave the person worse off overall than if they were unhappy. But why is this the most common exemplar of inauthenticity?

It might be defended, on the grounds that the suburban accountant role is sufficiently common that were someone simply mindlessly to conform, they might drift into it. But โ€œaccountantโ€ is far from the most common job. Accountants are vastly outnumbered by truck drivers and construction workers. But truck drivers and construction workers are conspicuously absent from examples of inauthenticity- so โ€œdriftโ€ doesnโ€™t do the explanatory work here.ย 

Perhaps, instead, the idea is that being an accountant is boring. Prima facie, thatโ€™s a little odd, because after all, few of us who deride accountancy have much experience of it. Worse, we have no grounds on which to compare it to other jobs that escape condemnation as inauthentic. Is accountant really less interesting than truck driver? Some people enjoy driving, but day after day of highways doesnโ€™t sound exciting to me.ย 

Even if accountancy is especially boring, itโ€™s still odd to think that accountants canโ€™t be authentic. Why shouldnโ€™t the suburban accountant be authentic? Why think that people have essences conforming to which makes lumberjack, artist or (as in the Monty Python sketched linked to above) lion tamer ย the right profession for them? Perhaps accountancy isnโ€™t particularly interesting, but most people are no more interesting than average, after all. There should be many people for whom accountancy is the authentic life.

The real reason why accountant is the exemplar of inauthenticity while truck driver is not, I strongly suspect, is simply that itโ€™s a cultural stereotype: an idea that circulates widely in our societies. In accepting it, we conform to ideas prevalent in our culture. Conversely, in accepting that writer and artist and lion tamer are especially authentic roles, we conform to another cluster of ideas.ย 

Our very conception of authenticity, I suggest, is a deeply cultural one. Itโ€™s not merely cultural in the same way that all concepts are: acquired through socialization. Itโ€™s more deeply cultural in that in applying it, we are guided by further ideas circulating in our culture. But the concept of authenticity is an individualist concept: we become authentic by becoming who we each, individually, are โ€“ not in conforming. If the attempt to be authentic must consist in conforming to a cultural stereotype of what it amounts to, then itโ€™s incoherent. We individualize ourselves by doing what the crowd thinks we should do to individualize ourselves.

We might think of authenticity in a more formal way: an authentic life is whatever life accords with what we find within, when we take our own measure (as Charles Taylor puts it). That would allow for the possibility of the authentic accountant: deep down, perhaps that is who I really am. That seems less self-defeating than a conception of authenticity that has us individualizing ourselves in a conformist way. Thereโ€™s nothing incoherent in thinking that individualization is important, even if we only think that due to socialization.

But the fact that our notions of the ways in which we might beย authentic are so deeply cultural should give us pause. What we take individualization to consist in, the content of an authentic way of being, is culturally shaped. Weโ€™re not individuals all on our own: weโ€™re individuals only in a social context. Perhaps that doesnโ€™t matter. But it does suggest that being authentic is not a way of escaping some sort of conformism, but another way of conforming.

โŒ