FreshRSS

๐Ÿ”’
โŒ About FreshRSS
There are new available articles, click to refresh the page.
Before yesterdayYour RSS feeds

Why Preventing Predation Can Be a Morally Right Cause for Effective Altruism?

By: admin

This article received an honourable mention in the graduate category of the 2023 National Oxford Uehiro Prize in Practical Ethics

Written by University of Oxford student Pablo Neira

If the interests of sentient animals matter, then there are (at least pro tanto) reasons to prevent the harms they suffer. There are many different natural harms that wild animals suffer, including hunger, disease, parasitism and extreme weather conditions (Singer 1975; Clark 1979; Sapontzis 1984; Cowen 2003; Fink 2005; Simmons 2009; Horta 2010; McMahan 2010; Ebert and Mavhan 2012; Keulartz 2016; Palmer 2013; Sรถzmen 2013; Bruers 2015; Tomasik 2015; McMahan 2016; Bramble 2021; Johannsen 2021). One of these (on which I will focus in this paper) is the suffering caused by predation. Predation is an antagonistic relationship in which a predator obtains energy by consuming a prey animalโ€”either wholly or partiallyโ€”which is alive when it is attacked (Begon et al. 2006, 266). The harms predation cause to prey animals can vary greatly, depending on the kind of injuries they suffer in the process and how painful they are, the amount of time it takes them to die, the release of endorphins that reduce pain or the extent to which psychological sufferingโ€”mostly distressโ€”affects them during the process. In addition, beyond the pain of predation itself, there are other substantial harms related to predation. It has been argued that death itself may harm animals because it deprives them of any possible future positive experiences (Nagel 1970; VisฬŒak and Garner 2016). However, we do not need to agree that death harms animals in order to consider predation a harm, as the suffering it causes to animals is sufficient in its own right. Moreover, some animals may survive predation and yet suffer serious injuries that cause them pain for a prolonged period of time, sometimes chronically (Schoener 1979; Engh et al. 2006; Jonhson et al. 2006). They may also live in fear of being attacked by predators (Lima 1998; Holbrook and Schmitt 2002; Mashoodh 2009). Thus, the pain experienced by sentient animals when they are attacked in nature should not be overlooked. In this essay, I will argue that it is permissible, and perhaps obligatory, to intervene to prevent predation. Moreover, if we accept this, it leads us to consider predation prevention as a cause area to take action seriously from Effective Altruism.

Predation: A Thought Experiment

Consider the following thought experiment:

Trapped Animals. An antelope is trapped between branches and abandoned by its herd. A hyena finds the antelope and begins to devour different parts of its body while it is still alive. This lasts several hours, until the antelope finally dies. Anna is near the antelope and, without placing herself in danger, could untangle the branches so the antelope could escape.

According to some deontological or virtue ethics perspectives,[1] it can be argued that Annaโ€™s intervention would be incorrect. This position can be defended by arguing that there is a rule that prevents intervention or that it is not virtuous to intervene. The idea that we should prevent predation may seem odd and wrong to some people at first. At the same time, based on other deontological approaches, we may have positive duties to animals (including wild ones), which we would fail to honour if we do not aid them when they are in need. Similarly, based on some virtue approaches, refusing to help animals would be contrary to what a virtuous person would do. In fact, that seems to be the case if we do not help the antelope here. Meanwhile, according to a consequentialist perspective, if Anna intervenes she would be acting in the correct manner, as long as her action leads to the best possible consequences all things considered. A counterargument could be that if we save the antelope, the hyena will starve, and thus Anna would be harming the hyena. This supports peopleโ€™s intuition against preventing predation. However, consider the following alternative:

Trapped Animals 2. The situation is the same as in Trapped Animals, except that Anna is physically close to the antelope, and, without exposing herself to danger, she could place a vegetable meat alternative on the ground with identical characteristics to antelope meat. The hyena would eat this alternative and leave the antelope unharmed. Anna could then untangle the branches so the antelope could escape.

In this case, again, a consequentialist perspective would imply that if Anna intervenes, she will act correctly, as the best outcome will be achieved all things considered. Deontological and virtue ethics arguments could reach a similar conclusion, as we saw in the Trapped Animals case. Therefore, our initial intuition against preventing predation may be shown to be misguided simply by introducing a small modification to the scenario. This is because our intuition against predation may still be present when we consider this case, despite the fact that all relevant considerations would lead us to conclude that we should save the antelope. In addition, our intuition against preventing predation could also be challenged by the following variant of the same case:

Trapped Animals 3. Everything is the same as in Trapped Animals 2, except that instead of an antelope it is a human being that is trapped.

When we include a human in the scenario, our intuition changes significantly. It no longer seems merely permissible but obligatory for Anna to act. It could be argued that this has no relevance for the previous cases, as there is a crucial difference between wild animals and humans. Indeed, it has been argued that wild animals possess certain capacities that allow them to use their natural abilities to survive, while humans do not (Simmons 2009, 19โ€“21). However, this objection does not seem to work, as in the cases we are considering both the human being and the nonhuman animal will surely die if Anna does not act. Thus, the antelope cannot adequately deal with the threat. So, if we are not speciesist, it seems we should hold a similar position in all cases.

This conclusion is further reinforced by the following case:

Trapped Animals 4. Everything is the same as in Trapped Animals 2, except that Anna is a biologist and knows that the antelope has a highly contagious disease. If the hyena eats it, this disease could infect other mammals, including humans.

Again, in this case it seems that it would not only permissible but obligatory for Anna to act. But, it is not clear whether there is a relevant difference between this case and the previous ones. We can only claim that there is if we maintain that the interests of humans are important in a way in which the interests of other beings are not.

Practical Implications: The Case for Effective Altruists

We may also conclude that this is an important cause, considering (as effective altruists do) its scale, neglectedness and tractability (Singer 2016, 19โ€“20; MacAskill 2019, 12โ€“15; Timmerman 2019, 166โ€“68; Berkey 2020, 368โ€“70). Regarding the scale, it is difficult to determine the exact number of wild animals that exist,[2] although we can estimate that the number is vast. Most suffer due to natural factors, and many are killed by predators. The overall amount of pain will be several orders of magnitude greater if we consider a long-term perspective, as the number of sentient animals that will live in the future is likely to be greater than the number of sentient animals that are alive now and have lived in the past as a whole. As for neglectedness, it is evident that this topic (and that of wild animal suffering in general) has received very little attention from animal charities or other organisations (for an exception, see Animal Ethics 2020). Finally, regarding tractability, there are different courses of action that could be implemented to prevent predation. I will now consider four of them. The first two are more speculative, and their expected results would need to be researched in far more detail before they could be implemented, which should first occur through pilot programmes. Meanwhile, the third and the fourth ones could be applied immediately and are much less controversial.

First, it has been argued that resources could be devoted to researching how to perform interventions similar to the natural evolution that led to the herborisation of some previously predatory species (e.g. the giant panda). This could be done by genetically modifying predators so that their offspring gradually becomes herbivorous, consequently changing their predatory behaviour (Pearce 2009; Palmer 2013; McMahan 2016; Bramble 2021; Johannsen 2021).

Second, resources could be devoted to organising the gradual extinction of predatory species (Pearce 2009; McMahan 2016; Bramble 2021), for example, by administering contraceptives to predators and allowing them to gradually disappear. Depot-contraception (a form of contraceptive injection that prevents ovulation in females) could be administered to carnivores, causing predatory animals to disappear within a few generations, and the resulting population effects on predated spices could be managed through more selective forms of contraception. Such advanced contraceptive techniques could be controlled by computer programs, which would be tested first on a small scale and then applied on a larger scale.

Third, the resources currently used to promote the conservation of predators (which are sometimes significant) could be allocated elsewhere, potentially having a better impact, while allowing the predators to disappear naturally (Cowen 2003).

Fourth, reforestation plans could be designed so the resulting ecosystems contain less rather than more predation. Different types of plants can support different types of animals. Accordingly, we could choose to plant types of vegetation that are less likely to support predators (Animal Ethics 2020).

If the arguments made in the previous sections are correct, then all the courses of action indicated above should be considered acceptable. However, many people will find this counterintuitive in the first two cases, despite the arguments presented above. Nevertheless, the latter two approaches could be considered acceptable by anyone willing to give at least some weight to the interests of wild animals. This means that preventing predation is tractable, at least in some ways.

Conclusion

I have argued that intervening to prevent harms to animals resulting from predation is morally right. Those who argue that we should not act in cases of predation must rely on ad hoc responses to intervention in scenarios in which such action seems to be the right choice. Admittedly, this will likely be a counterintuitive conclusion for many people, although the arguments I have presented appear to imply it. However, while some of the approaches for preventing predation may appear contrary to intuition, that is not true for all of them.

Notes:

[1] It could be also be defended from a rights perspective, wild animals can certainly harm each other, but they cannot violate the rights of others (Regan 1983; Jamieson 1990; Cohen 1997; Milburn 2015); of capacities, the capacity of specific species to flower, requiring a type of predation (Nussbaum 2006; Schlosberg, 2006; Cripps 2010); or of the community of animals, as it is reasonable to assume that wild animals are fully competent to address the challenges they face (Donaldson and Kymlicka 2011).

[2] Specifically, there are estimated to be 1011โ€“4ยท1011 birds, 1011โ€“1012 mammals, 1011โ€“1014 reptiles, 1011โ€“1014 amphibians, 1013โ€“1015 fish, 1014โ€“1017 earthworms 1014โ€“1017 mites, 1015โ€“1018 polyps, 1017โ€“1019 terrestrial arthropods, 1017โ€“1019 rotifers, 1019 gastrotrichs, 1018 copepods and 1020โ€“1022 nematodes (Tomasik 2019).

ย 

References

Animal Ethics. 2020. โ€œAntagonism in Nature: Interspecific Conflictโ€. https://www.animal-ethics.org/conflictos-interespecificos/#fr30. Retrieved 31 August 2022.

Begon, Michael, Townsend, Colin R. and John L. Harper. 2006. Ecology: From Individuals to Ecosystems. Oxford: Blackwell.

Berkey, Brian. 2020. โ€œEffectiveness and Demandingness.โ€ Utilitas 32, no. 3: 368โ€“81. https://doi.org/10.1017/S0953820820000084.

Bramble, Ben. 2021. โ€œPainlessly Killing Predators.โ€ Journal of Applied Philosophy 38, no. 2: 217โ€“25. https://doi.org/10.1111/japp.12461.

Bruers, Stijn. (2015). โ€œThe Predation and Procreation Problems: Persistent Intuitions Gone Wild.โ€ Relations 3, no. 1, 85โ€“91. https://doi.org/10.7358/rela-2015-001-brue.

Clark, Stephen R. L. 1979. โ€œThe Rights of Wild Things.โ€ Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 22, no. 1-4: 171โ€“88. https://doi.org/10.1080/00201747908601871.

Cohen, Carl. 1997. โ€œDo Animals Have Rights?โ€ Ethics and Behavior, 7, no. 2: 91โ€“102. https://doi.org/10.1207/s15327019eb0702_1.

Cowen, Tyler. 2003. โ€œPolicing Nature.โ€ Environmental Ethics 25, no. 2: 169โ€“82. https://doi.org/10.5840/enviroethics200325231.

Cripps, Elizabeth. 2010. โ€œSaving the Polar Bear, Saving the World: Can the Capabilities Approach Do Justice to Humans, Animals and Ecosystems?โ€ Res Publica 16: 1โ€“22. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-010-9106-2.

Donaldson, Sue, and Will Kymlicka. 2011. Zoopolis. A Political Theory of Animal Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Ebert, Rainer, and Tibor R. Machan. 2012. โ€œInnocent Threats and the Moral Problem of Carnivorous Animals.โ€ Journal of Applied Philosophy, 29, no. 2: 146โ€“159. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-5930.2012.00561.x.

Engh, Anne L., Jacinta C. Beehner, Thore J. Bergman, Patricial L. Whitten, Rebekah R. Hoffmeier, Robert M. Seyfarth and Dorothy L. Cheney. 2006. โ€œBehavioural and Hormonal Responses to Predation in Female Chacma Baboons (Papio Hamadryas Ursinus).โ€ Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 273, no. 1587: 707โ€“12. https://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2005.3378.

Fink, Charles K. (2005). โ€œThe Predation Argument.โ€ Between the Species 13, no. 5:1โ€“15. https://doi.org/10.15368/BTS.2005V13N5.3.

Holbrook, Sally J. and Russell J. Schmitt. 2002. โ€œCompetition for Shelter Space Causes Density-dependent Predation Mortality in Damselfishes.โ€ Ecology 83, no. 10: 2855โ€“68. https://doi.org/10.2307/3072021.

Horta, Oscar. 2010. โ€œThe Ethics of the Ecology of Fear against the Nonspeciesist Paradigm: A Shift in the Aims of Intervention in Nature.โ€ Between the Species 13, no. 10: 163โ€“87. https://doi.org/10.15368/bts.2010v13n10.10.

Jamieson, Dale. 1990. โ€œRights, Justice, and Duties to Provide Assistance: A Critique of Reganโ€™s Theory of Rights.โ€ Ethics 100, no. 2: 349โ€“62. https://doi.org/10.1086/293181.

Johannsen, Kyle. 2021. Wild Animal Ethics. The Moral and Political Problem of Wild Animal Suffering. London: Routledge

Jonhson, Pieter T. J., Eric R. Preu, Daniel R. Sutherland, John M. Romansic, Barbara Han and Andrew R. Blaustein. 2006. โ€œAdding Infection to Injury: Synergistic Effects of Predation and Parasitism on Amphibian Malformations.โ€, Ecology 87, no. 9: 2227โ€“35. https://doi.org/10.1890/0012-9658(2006)87[2227:aitise]2.0.co;2.

Keulartz, Jozef. 2016. โ€œShould the Lion Eat Straw Like the Ox? Animal Ethics and the Predation Problem.โ€ Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 29, no. 5: 813โ€“34. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-016-9637-4.

Lima, Steven. 1998. โ€œStress and Decision Making Under the Risk of Predation: Recent Developments from Behavioral, Reproductive, and Ecological Perspectives.โ€ Advances in the Study of Behavior 27: 215โ€“90. https://doi.org/10.1016/S0065-3454(08)60366-6.

MacAskill, William 2019. โ€œThe Definition of Effective Altruism.โ€ In Effective Altruism, 10โ€“28. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198841364.003.0001.

Mashoodh, Rahia, Christopher J. Sinal and Tara S. Perrot-Sinal. 2009. โ€œPredation Threat Exerts Specific Effects on Rat Maternal Behaviour and Anxiety-related Behaviour of Male and Female Offspring.โ€ Physiology & Behavior, 96, no. 4โ€“5: 693โ€“702. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.physbeh.2009.01.001.

McMahan, Jeff. 2010. โ€œThe Meat Eatersโ€. New York Times (online), 19 September. https://archive.nytimes.com/opinionator.blogs.nytimes.com/2010/09/19/the-meat-eaters/. Retrieved 31 August 2022.

โ€”โ€”โ€“. 2016. โ€œThe Moral Problem of Predation.โ€ In Philosophy Comes to Dinner, 268โ€“95. New York: Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9780203154410

Milburn, Josh. 2015. โ€œRabbits, Stoats and the Predator Problem: Why a Strong Animal Rights Position Need not Call for Human Intervention to Protect Prey from Predators.โ€ Res Publica 21, no. 3: 273โ€“89. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11158-015-9281-2.

Nagel, Thomas. 1970. โ€œDeathโ€, Noรปs, 4, no. 1: 73โ€“80. https://doi.org/10.2307/2214297.

Nussbaum, Martha. 2006. Frontiers of Justice. Disability, Nationality, Species Membership. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Palmer, Clare. 2013. โ€œWhat (If Anything) Do We Owe Wild Animals?โ€ Between the Species 13, no. 1: https://doi.org/10.15368/bts.2013v16n1.4.

Pearce, David. 2009. โ€œReprogramming Predators.โ€ BLTC Research. https://www.abolitionist.com/reprogramming/index.html.

Regan, Tom. 1983. The Case for Animal Rights. Berkeley: University of California Press.

Sapontzis, Steve. 1984. โ€œPredationโ€, Ethics and Animals 5, no. 2: 27โ€“38. https://doi.org/10.15368/ea.1984v5n2.1.

Schlosberg, David. 2007. Defining Environmental Justice: Theories, Movements, and Nature. New York: Oxford University Press.

Schoener, Thomas. 1979. โ€œInferring the Properties of Predation and Other Injury-producing Agents from Injury Frequencies.โ€ Ecology 60, no. 6: 1110โ€“15. https://doi.org/10.2307/1936958.

Simmons, Aaron. 2009. โ€œAnimals, Predators, the Right to Life, and the Duty to Save Lives.โ€ Ethics & the Environment, 14, no. 1: 15โ€“27. https://doi.org/10.2979/ete.2009.14.1.15.

Singer, Peter. 1975. Animal Liberation. New York: Random House.

โ€”โ€”โ€“. 2015. The Most Good You Can Do: How Effective Altruism Is Changing Ideas about Living Ethically. New Haven: Yale University Press.

Sรถzmen, Beril. 2013. โ€œHarm in the Wild: Facing Non-Human Suffering in Nature.โ€ Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 16, no. 5: 1075โ€“88. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10677-013-9416-5.

Timmerman, Travis. 2019. โ€œEffective Altruismโ€™s Underspecification Problem.โ€ In Effective Altruism, 166โ€“83. Oxford: Oxford University Press. https://doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198841364.003.0011.

Tomasik, Brian. 2015. โ€œThe Importance of Wild Animal Suffering.โ€ Relations, 3, no. 2: 133โ€“52. https://doi.org/10.7358/rela-2015-002-toma.

โ€”โ€”โ€“.ย 2019. โ€œHow Many Wild Animals Are There?โ€ Essays on Reducing Suffering. https://reducing-suffering.org/how-many-wild-animals-are-there/. Retrieved 31 August 2022.

VisฬŒak, Tatjana, and Robert Garner. 2016. The Ethics of Killing Animals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

ย 

ย 

โŒ